DISCLAIMER: This post may inflame you if you are not a supporter of phylogenetic nomenclature, so my advise to you before you go on is don't ruin your day and skip reading it. If you choose to read it, please keep in mind this is not a debate on the validity of the PhyloCode (that's a given to us). However, if you fundamentally share the philosophy at the core of phylogenetic nomenclature, then you may want to know what's going on among us proponents.
Last October, Brent Mishler (University of California, Berkeley), David Baum (University of Wisconsin, Madison) and I submitted a proposal to the International Society for Phylogenetic Nomenclature (ISPN) in order to remove all mention of "species" from the
PhyloCode. We provide justifications for
this goal in a supporting paper (Cellinese et al. 2012). The proposal is currently being discussed by the ISPN Committee of Phylogenetic Nomenclature, and given our paper is also in review, this seems to be the right time to stir the pot a little more.
All proponents of phylogenetic nomenclature would agree that the PhyloCode is about
naming clades, and removing ranks from nomenclature. Yet, unfortunately there remain aspects in the
current wording of the Code that are not about naming clades and that retain
rank considerations. These aspects all
surround the traditional Linnaean rank of species. The PhyloCode currently states that "In
this code, the terms "species" and "clade" refer to
different kinds of biological entities, not ranks" (note 3.1.1.). While the concept of species implicitly
endorsed by the PhyloCode, that of de Queiroz (2007), does indeed assume that
species and clade are distinct entities, this is not universally accepted by
any means. Many different species
concepts are currently applied across the different biological domains (Mayden1997). Some, like de Queiroz (2007) view
species as lineages. Others (e.g.
Mishler 1999; Pleijel 1999; Mishler and Theriot 2000 a,b,c; Baum 2009) view
species as ranked or unranked clades.
But this disagreement is not relevant to a Code of nomenclature that is
(supposedly) rank-agnostic and concerned only with naming clades. The debate over species concepts does not
need to be solved for the purpose of naming clades under the PhyloCode. Phylogenetic nomenclature can and should
remain logically independent from the philosophical debate about species. Therefore, the PhyloCode need not and should
not anoint any particular species concept as the correct one. By leaving the word “species” out of the
entire document it will be clear that the PhyloCode is available to all
systematists regardless of their views on the nature of species.
The
PhyloCode as currently constructed
works under the assumption that species are not clades, yet paradoxically
brings species into the naming of clades in a couple of damaging ways. One is by its current ruling (Article 10.9)
that traditional species names should be disallowed for clades. The current version of the PhyloCode, influenced by Dayrat et al.(2008), effectively applies special rules at the “species” level. When a clade happens to approximate to a
traditional species in content, the PhyloCode
now mandates that that clade be given a new name, distinct from the traditional
species name. This is unlike the case when clades approximate in content to genera or families (etc.), in which case the Code strongly encourages the conversion of the traditional name into a clade name. In this way, the PhyloCode establishes parallel
nomenclatural systems for species and species-approximating clades. We argue that this is illogical; as there are
no ranks under the PhyloCode, there
should not be an explicit or implicit rank of species. Phylogenetic nomenclature should accommodate
clades whose content is roughly comparable to current species (under whatever
species concept). We propose that the PhyloCode be modified to be neutral
about species and thus to accommodate all users, including those who wish to be
able to attach appropriate names to clades that approximate taxa at the
traditional species level.
Another
way in which the current version of the PhyloCode
generates problems for itself is that it
allows species to be used as specifiers for clade names (Art. 11), and
relegates the governing of species names to the traditional Codes (Art. 21).
This means that the PhyloCode is not
a freestanding system of nomenclature.
This is unwise; the PhyloCode
should be independent and self-contained.
No rules in the PhyloCode
should depend on rules in the traditional Codes, including rules for species
names. This is easily solved by
requiring that specifiers under the PhyloCode
be museum or herbarium specimens (physical reference objects, possibly Linnaean
types at the discretion of the taxonomist) at all levels, never Linnaean binomials
per se. Linnaean species binomials are
incompatible with phylogenetic taxonomy because they naturally imply the
existence of a genus rank, and they are incommensurable with phylogenetic taxa
because they are named using only one type (Cellinese et al. 2012).
Since
its purpose is to name clades, any mention of ‘species’ in the PhyloCode should be removed. We propose to streamline the PhyloCode to focus solely on rational
procedures for naming clades with uninomials at any level including the
traditional species level. The rules
governing names of clades at and around the traditional species level should
follow exactly the same rules and recommendations as at higher levels. To view the original proposals we submitted to ISPN click here. Also see the posting at Phylonames.
References:
Cellinese, N., Baum D.A., Mishler B.D. 2012. Species and Phylogenetic Nomenclature. Syst. Biol. 61: 885-891.
Baum D. A. 2009. Species as ranked
taxa. Syst. Biol. 58:74-86.
Dayrat B., Schander C. ,
Angielczyk, K. D. 2004. Suggestions for a new species nomenclature. Taxon 53:485–591.
Dayrat B., Cantino P.D., Clarke
J.A., de Queiroz K. 2008. Species names in the PhyloCode: the approach adopted
by the International Society for Phylogenetic Nomenclature. Syst. Biol.
57:507-514.
de Queiroz K. 2007. Species
Concepts and Species Delimitation.
Syst. Biol. 56:879-886.
Mayden R.L. 1997. A hierarchy of species
concepts: The denouement in the saga of the species problem. In: Claridge M.F.,
Dawah H.A., Wilson M.R., editors. Species: the units of biodiversity. London:
Chapman and Hall, p. 381-424.
Mishler B.D. 1999. Getting rid of
species? In: Wilson R., editor. Species:
new interdisciplinary essays. Cambridge: MIT Press, p. 307-315.
Mishler B.D., Theriot E.C. 2000a.
The phylogenetic species concept (sensu Mishler and Theriot): monophyly,
apomorphy, and phylogenetic species concepts. In: Wheeler Q.D., Meier R.,
editors. Species concepts and phylogenetic theory. New York: Columbia University Press, p.
44-54.
Mishler B.D., Theriot E.C. 2000b. A
critique from the Mishler and Theriot phylogenetic species concept perspective:
monophyly, apomorphy, and phylogenetic species concepts. In: Wheeler Q.D.,
Meier R., editors. Species concepts and phylogenetic theory. New York: Columbia University Press, p. 119-132.
Mishler B.D., Theriot E.C. 2000c. A
defense of the phylogenetic species concept (sensu Mishler and Theriot):
monophyly, apomorphy, and phylogenetic species concepts. In: In: Wheeler Q.D., Meier R., editors. Species
concepts and phylogenetic theory. New
York: Columbia University Press, p.
179-184.
Pleijel F. 1999. Phylogenetic
taxonomy, a farewell to species, and a revision of Heteropodarke (Hesionidae,
Polychaeta, Annelida). Syst. Biol. 48:755-789.